Contents of spoon-archives/french-feminism.archive/Lubbock.abstracts/peebles
Catherine M. Peebles
Binghamton University
cmp8q@faraday.clas.virginia.edu
ABSTRACT: Sexual Difference Beyond the Phallus: Lacan and Irigaray
It is now time to devote some thought to developing an ethics of
inclusion or of the unlimited, that is, an ethics proper to the woman.
Another logic of the superego must now commence. (Joan Copjec, Sex and the
Euthanasia of Reason in Joan Copjec, ed., Supposing the Subject, London:
Verso, 1994, p. 42.)
In this essay, I address the difficult question of thinking sexual
difference with and/or beyond Lacan, a challenge which has been taken up
ever since the publication of the twentieth seminar, Encore. I start by
taking Irigarays critique of Lacanian psychoanalysis as one which needs to
be addressed and thought alongside that which it critiques, and not as
simply dismissing the former. I also take Joan Copjecs response to
feminist critiques of Lacan as useful for engaging in a dialogue about
sexual difference, for it facilitates an opening up of Lacanian
psychoanalytic thought to the questions which Irigaray brings to bear upon
it.
Part I of the text (Phallus) addresses Irigarays interpretation of
Lacans use of this term. Rather than adopting a reading which assumes (by
oversimplification) that Irigaray accuses Lacan of blurring the phallus
and the penis and failing to acknowledge this blur, I argue that Irigaray
(most specifically in her text Cos fan tutti in Ce sexe qui nen est pas
un) points up the structures in the Lacanian symbolic (a
phallus/castration symbolic) which make the existence of woman impossible,
and the existence of man an imposture.Thus both Irigaray and Lacan
conclude that because of their differing relation to the phallus, the mans
existence is confirmed (he has, he gives, he is) while the womans status
vacillates undecidably between existence and nonexistence (she doesnt have
/ she seems to have, she doesnt give / she seems to give, she is not / she
seems to be). Irigarays quarrel with Lacan stems from the fact that he
does not apparently argue against the crime inherent in this system, or
insist on the need for its radical rethinking for the stake of there being
two in a (sexual) relation. Irigaray is not arguing for a kind of
ontological equality politics: let there be woman (as there is man). The
question of womans existence is important here not because she should
exist too, as man exists, but rather because existence itself is shown to
be thought in such a way as forecloses difference, and thus the ethical
possibility of (any relation to) a womans (living) difference. Thus the
question of the phallus leads necessarily to the question of being(s).
Part II (Sexual Difference/Not Existing) begins with Lacans own
questioning of his notorious negations (e.g. il ny a pas La femme...il ny
a pas dexistence du rapport sexuel...). But what he asks, does it mean to
deny it? Is it in any way legitimate to substitute a negation for the
apprehension of nonexistence? (Encore, 132) This question leads me to
Copjecs reading of Lacans formulae of sexual difference, and her
explanation of the not-All place that Woman occupies therein (Sex and the
Euthanasia of Reason in Joan Copjec, ed. Supposing the Subject). I
conclude this section by suggesting where Copjecs reading might lead,
namely: that an ethics proper to the woman may involve what Irigaray
calls taking the negative upon ourselves (Ethique de la diffrence
sexuelle, p. 116). I proceed discuss the relation of this taking the
negative upon oneself to feminine jouissance, and hence, to the
possibility of an ethical relation in sexual difference based not on what
Copjec (after Lacan) identifies as a superegoistic logic of the limit, but
rather on an ethics of the unlimited, or the feminine.
Part III (Dieu et la jouissance de Lafemme: Existence in
relation, relations inexistence) then begins with a reading of parts of
the twentieth seminar, most specifically Dieu et la jouissance de Lafemme
and Une lettre dmour as an enactment of the possibility and failure of
such an ethical relation. I focus on Lacans dramatic positioning of
himself as an I in relation to a you which is his audience and a they
which are his readers, and further interrogate the kind of love he calls
for, and sees as failing between I and you as sexed subjects. I follow up
this reading with a continuation of the discussion, begun in Part II, of
feminine jouissance and Irigarays thinking of the negative. The concluding
passage of my text reads as follows:
We can now read Lacans demand that his audience desuppose him of
knowledge (as his good, loving, and also hating, readers do) as a demand
for another love, a love which does not situate a subject (supposed or
desupposed of knowledge) as always and only beyond, a love which would
allow something else to come between subjects. With Irigaray we suggest
that this something may be a jouissance which, while neither known nor
mastered, would be mutually created and experienced between subjects who
listen without supposing finally to know what is heard and said, thereby
forging a tenuous, and always shifting and shared, limit.
Display software:
ArchTracker © Malgosia Askanas, 2000-2005